新品:
-13% ¥5,266 税込
ポイント: 53pt  (1%)
無料配送5月29日 水曜日にお届け
発送元: Amazon.co.jp
販売者: Amazon.co.jp
13パーセントの割引で¥5,266 税込
参考価格: ¥6,044

他に注記がない場合、参考価格とは、製造業者、卸売業者、輸入代理店(「製造業者」)などの小売業者以外が設定した、商品のカタログなど印刷物で発表された、または製造業者が小売業者に提示する参考価格・推奨小売価格を意味します。ただし、Amazonが製造・販売するデバイスの参考価格については、他に注記が無い場合、個人のお客様向けに最近相当期間表示されていた価格を意味します(注記の内容を含む参考価格の詳細については、該当する商品詳細ページをご確認ください)。なお、割引率の表示は1%毎に行われており小数点以下は四捨五入しています。
詳細はこちら
ポイント: 53pt  (1%)  詳細はこちら
無料配送5月29日 水曜日にお届け
詳細を見る
または 最も早いお届け日時指定便 5月28日 火曜日, 8:00 - 12:00の間にお届け(16 時間 50 分以内にご注文の場合)
詳細を見る
在庫あり。 在庫状況について
¥5,266 () 選択したオプションを含めます。 最初の月の支払いと選択されたオプションが含まれています。 詳細
価格
小計
¥5,266
小計
初期支払いの内訳
レジで表示される配送料、配送日、注文合計 (税込)。
出荷元
Amazon.co.jp
出荷元
Amazon.co.jp
販売元
販売元
支払い方法
お客様情報を保護しています
お客様情報を保護しています
Amazonはお客様のセキュリティとプライバシーの保護に全力で取り組んでいます。Amazonの支払いセキュリティシステムは、送信中にお客様の情報を暗号化します。お客様のクレジットカード情報を出品者と共有することはありません。また、お客様の情報を他者に販売することはありません。 詳細はこちら
支払い方法
お客様情報を保護しています
Amazonはお客様のセキュリティとプライバシーの保護に全力で取り組んでいます。Amazonの支払いセキュリティシステムは、送信中にお客様の情報を暗号化します。お客様のクレジットカード情報を出品者と共有することはありません。また、お客様の情報を他者に販売することはありません。 詳細はこちら
¥2,012 税込
ポイント: 20pt  (1%)  詳細はこちら
■通常24時間以内に出荷可能です。■クリーニング済み。■中古品ではございますが、良好なコンディションです。■万が一品質に不備があった場合は返金対応。■防水梱包です。■決済は、クレジットカード、コンビニ決済・ATM・ネットバンキング・Edy払いがご利用可能です。 ■通常24時間以内に出荷可能です。■クリーニング済み。■中古品ではございますが、良好なコンディションです。■万が一品質に不備があった場合は返金対応。■防水梱包です。■決済は、クレジットカード、コンビニ決済・ATM・ネットバンキング・Edy払いがご利用可能です。 一部を表示
配送料 ¥350 5月29日-30日にお届け(5 時間 50 分以内にご注文の場合)
詳細を見る
残り1点 ご注文はお早めに 在庫状況について
¥5,266 () 選択したオプションを含めます。 最初の月の支払いと選択されたオプションが含まれています。 詳細
価格
小計
¥5,266
小計
初期支払いの内訳
レジで表示される配送料、配送日、注文合計 (税込)。
Kindleアプリのロゴ画像

無料のKindleアプリをダウンロードして、スマートフォン、タブレット、またはコンピューターで今すぐKindle本を読むことができます。Kindleデバイスは必要ありません

ウェブ版Kindleなら、お使いのブラウザですぐにお読みいただけます。

携帯電話のカメラを使用する - 以下のコードをスキャンし、Kindleアプリをダウンロードしてください。

KindleアプリをダウンロードするためのQRコード

何か問題が発生しました。後で再度リクエストしてください。

Whither Socialism? ペーパーバック – 1996/1/31

3.9 5つ星のうち3.9 11個の評価

{"desktop_buybox_group_1":[{"displayPrice":"¥5,266","priceAmount":5266.00,"currencySymbol":"¥","integerValue":"5,266","decimalSeparator":null,"fractionalValue":null,"symbolPosition":"left","hasSpace":false,"showFractionalPartIfEmpty":true,"offerListingId":"wyKVB6XEkDFJ6fDupVta4uxJ88M16slhqjLj%2Bcyq1XebHE%2B5%2F8ZJWZd6aVk4hQhUEgqRSeKBG0BGZfSz%2FbDNTgeYIgf9HHZ4C7d8saavQVSP0amUSJmY1zBsQZ3hMPa5","locale":"ja-JP","buyingOptionType":"NEW","aapiBuyingOptionIndex":0}, {"displayPrice":"¥2,012","priceAmount":2012.00,"currencySymbol":"¥","integerValue":"2,012","decimalSeparator":null,"fractionalValue":null,"symbolPosition":"left","hasSpace":false,"showFractionalPartIfEmpty":true,"offerListingId":"wyKVB6XEkDFJ6fDupVta4uxJ88M16slhRkw4zvGGBAWxp2g3nN3OGzHkQyR1WiRH3r1oEuulizDT45eq%2Fc8ARCQwN2PYiQk6VjrmUpZT%2F0Obp6ayWynM%2FYyBzKwD5UV2NW0iKSOEpUTLUAjGB65jGRhGz2%2Bg954UhmtjTew4KtkspUqDMaNbcQ%3D%3D","locale":"ja-JP","buyingOptionType":"USED","aapiBuyingOptionIndex":1}]}

購入オプションとあわせ買い

The rapid collapse of socialism has raised new economic policy questions and revived old theoretical issues. In this book, Joseph Stiglitz explains how the neoclassical, or Walrasian model (the formal articulation of Adam Smith's invisible hand), which has dominated economic thought over the past half century, may have wrongly encouraged the belief that market socialism could work. Stiglitz proposes an alternative model, based on the economics of information, that provides greater theoretical insight into the workings of a market economy and clearer guidance for the setting of policy in transitional economies.

Stiglitz sees the critical failing in the standard neoclassical model underlying market socialism to be its assumptions concerning information, particularly its failure to consider the problems that arise from lack of perfect information and from the costs of acquiring information. He also identifies problems arising from its assumptions concerning completeness of markets, competitiveness of markets, and the absence of innovation. Stiglitz argues that not only did the existing paradigm fail to provide much guidance on the vital question of the choice of economic systems, the advice it did provide was often misleading.

続きを読む もっと少なく読む

商品の説明

レビュー

Whither Socialism? is to be recommended. It offers deep new thinking on a big subject: the role of the state. It is rigorous and accessible, a rare combination.—The Economist

著者について

Joseph Stiglitz, a 2001 Nobel Laureate, is University Professor at Columbia University.

登録情報

  • 出版社 ‏ : ‎ MIT Press; Reprint版 (1996/1/31)
  • 発売日 ‏ : ‎ 1996/1/31
  • 言語 ‏ : ‎ 英語
  • ペーパーバック ‏ : ‎ 352ページ
  • ISBN-10 ‏ : ‎ 0262691825
  • ISBN-13 ‏ : ‎ 978-0262691826
  • 寸法 ‏ : ‎ 15.24 x 2.03 x 22.86 cm
  • カスタマーレビュー:
    3.9 5つ星のうち3.9 11個の評価

著者について

著者をフォローして、新作のアップデートや改善されたおすすめを入手してください。
ジョセフ・E.スティグリッツ
Brief content visible, double tap to read full content.
Full content visible, double tap to read brief content.

著者の本をもっと発見したり、よく似た著者を見つけたり、著者のブログを読んだりしましょう

カスタマーレビュー

星5つ中3.9つ
5つのうち3.9つ
11グローバルレーティング

この商品をレビュー

他のお客様にも意見を伝えましょう

上位レビュー、対象国: 日本

日本からの0件のレビューとお客様による0件の評価があります

他の国からのトップレビュー

すべてのレビューを日本語に翻訳
Ricardo s.
5つ星のうち4.0 Great Purchase
2021年11月18日に英国でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
This is an excellent book, that must be read critically - as all books related to the socialist calculation debate.
ALFONSO TELLEZ
5つ星のうち3.0 Una visión muy interesante de los principios económicos.
2015年10月14日にスペインでレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
No existe nada que a mí me haga hacer una cosa por obligatoriedad.
Esto es una chorrada. El libro es bueno, pero esta tonteria de hacerme obligatoria mi opinión va en contra del derecho al silencio, que es el más excelso modo de ejercer la libertad de expresión.
Gabriel S Britton
5つ星のうち3.0 Wither Socialism?
2009年10月13日にアメリカ合衆国でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
I read this book in contrast to Friedrich von Hayek's "The Road to Serfdom," which is a a manual for the type of classic liberalism/neoclasicalism that Stiglitz attacks. The following is my comparison of the two.

In concluding Whither Socialism, Joseph E. Stiglitz states that "if I were to claim that socialism as an ideology can now officially be declared dead, I do not think it would be an exaggeration." This declaration is made after a lengthily and sustained attack on socialism in the form of market socialism and communism as described by models based on the central tenets of capitalism. Stiglitz's supposed frontal assault on socialism is in all actuality a flanking maneuver against capitalism.
As Stiglitz is berating socialism from one side of his mouth he is suggesting a move away from liberal economics through greater governmental intervention on the other. The changes Stiglitz supports are of just the type warned against in Friedrich A. Hayek's The Road to Serfdom. Hayek notes that in theories like Stiglitz's "the question is no longer how we can make the best use of the spontaneous forces found in a free society. We have in effect undertaken to dispense with the forces that have produced unforeseen results and to replace the impersonal and anonymous mechanisms of the market by collective and `conscious" direction of all social forces to deliberately chosen goals." Hayek would see the direction Stiglitz seeks to push the economy as the first leg of a trip on the road to serfdom.

Walrasian model via Arrow and Debreu
Hayek was strongly influenced by the work of the Austrian school and therefore, would undoubtedly (as evinced by his writing) feel that the complexity of subjective individual human choices in the market would leave models lacking at best. Nonetheless, Hayek alludes to some of the elements of the Walrasian model throughout his book but in many respects he attacks them. It is precisely this model that Stiglitz spends approximately the first third of his book attempting to disprove.
The Walrasian model "postulates large numbers of profit- (or value-) maximizing firms interacting with rational, utility-maximizing consumers on and an economy in which there is a complete set of perfectly competitive markets--for all goods, in all periods, in all states of nature (for all risks), at all locations." In less technical terms this model first supposes "that it is possible for markets to engender a general economic equilibrium, a set of trades between economic actors in which every firm demands resources and labor and sells outputs in a profit-maximizing fashion, subject to its technological constraints." Consumers provide labor then purchase goods at utility maximizing market prices that do not exceed the value of the labor or resources they are willing to sell. "This set of trades is equilibrium in the sense that no demand (by a firm or consumer) goes unfulfilled and no supply (of a resource or commodity) goes unpurchased."
Hayek generally applies his ideas in a Walrasian setting as far as capitalism is concerned. He certainly envisions the give and take of the market as described above noting that "our freedom of choice in a competitive society rests on the fact that, if one person refuses to satisfy our wishes we can turn to another." This satisfying of wishes would of course include a value maximizing decision by the consumer in an attempt to better his position. Hayek however does not follow the mathematical formulation of the Walrasian model in respect to the presumption of perfectly competitive markets. This presumption relies on perfect information related to all goods at all locations at all times. Hayek writes that "we may have to sacrifice a possible immediate gain as the price of our freedom--but we avoid, on the other hand, the necessity of making future developments dependent upon the knowledge which particular people now possess."
Stiglitz uses the formal description of the Walrasian model to build an argument against the Lange-Lerner-Taylor theorem, which was derived from the Walrasian model. The Lange-Lerner-Taylor theorem is a theory of market socialism which presumes that "if the government allocates capitol in exactly the same way the private firms would allocate it' then the resource allocations emerging from the two systems would be identical." Stiglitz concedes that "Hayek had rightly criticized this view that the central planner could never have the requisite information." Within this statement lies the heart of Stiglitz's argument against the Walrasian model. Stiglitz, however, carries the effects of imperfect information over from its effect on a central planner to its effects on consumers and producers.
"What is generally referred to as the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics shows that under certain conditions every competitive equilibrium is Pareto efficient--that is no one can be made better off without making some one worse off." This theorem is a modern rendition of Adam Smith's invisible hand wherein "it is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest." Smith goes on to describe how this self love promotes societal good as a side effect writing "by pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of the society more effectually than when he really intends to promote it."
Hayek concurs with the notion that a person in a society acting in their own interest tends to promote the good of the whole society. Hayek does not limit this to its application to economic effects; however, he would argue that this ability to pursue one's best interest also has bearing on political good. Of self-seeking efforts bettering one's position Hayek states that "what in ordinary language is misleadingly called the economic motive means merely the desire for general opportunity, the desire to achieve unspecified ends. If we strive for money it is because it offers us the widest choice in enjoying the fruits of our efforts." Hayek notes that the "argument in favor of economic freedom was the outcome of a free growth of economic activity which had been the undesigned and unforeseen by-product of political freedom." He uses this notion to serve as a warning that governmental control over economic activities is tantamount to government control over every aspect of the citizenries' lives. As economic freedom has had the byproduct of political freedom in Hayek's view, loss of economic freedom would result in loss of political freedom. This tying together of economic and political good differs greatly from the traditional notion of Pareto optimality. Since Hayek does not presume perfect information about the effects of market decisions on conditions in the future he implies an added value to decentralized decisions that outwardly may appear inefficient. He states that "in the short run the price we may have to pay for variety and freedom of choice may sometimes be high, in the long run even material progress will depend on this very variety, because we can never predict from which of the many forms in which a good or service can be provided something better may develop."
Stiglitz takes a purely formal economic approach in analyzing the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics. He argues "that the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics -asserting the efficiency of competitive economies -is fundamentally flawed" and that "quite contrary to that theorem, competitive economies are almost never efficient." Stiglitz again attacks the lack of perfect information as is assumed in the rigid formal model of Pareto efficiency. Stiglitz notes that "the incompleteness of the market can itself be explained by transaction costs, and important component of which is information costs." Stiglitz sees these information costs as precluding any possibility of having a Pareto efficient market. Stiglitz uses asymmetries of information as an example of a situation where the market is not efficient. If one party has more, or more accurate, information they may be able to strike a bargain wherein they come out as the winner over the other. Additionally, Stiglitz posits that the high cost of information creates barriers to Pareto efficiency. Where one firm lowers its price for a good the "low-priced firm can gather for themselves a larger customer base, but the high-priced firms can survive, serving only those who have high search costs and who have not had the good fortune to find a low priced firm." Stiglitz concludes his analysis of the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics by describing that the failures of market socialism are due to the fact that like capitalism, market socialism failed to pay any attention to the problems posed by imperfect information.
Hayek in the Austrian tradition would tend to look in a negative light on the formalistic model driven approach to the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics. Undoubtedly he would consider the information costs as Stiglitz describes them to be a problem, though he may view them as a part of the whole of the transaction. Hayek does however express that:
In a competitive society the prices we have to pay for a thing , the rate at which we can get one thing for another, depend on the quantities of other things of which by taking one, we deprive the other members of society. This price is not determined by the coconscious will of anybody. And if one way of achieving our ends proves too expensive for us, we are free to try other ways. The obstacles in our path are not due to someone's disapproving our ends but to the fact that the same means are also wanted elsewhere.
This statement clearly mirrors the formal description of Pareto optimality, Hayek doesn't mention this as a specific model, rather, he seems to feel that it is an accurate description of competitive society. Perhaps Hayek does believe in the underlying notion of Pareto optimality though he does not seem to have a rigid conception.
"What is generally referred to as the second fundamental theorem of welfare economics provides conditions under which any Pareto-efficient allocation of resources can be obtained through market mechanisms?" Stiglitz, apparently presuming that the current allocation of resources is not Pareto efficient as indicated by his analysis of the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics, extrapolates this theorem to state that "all that is needed is to have the government engage in some initial lump sum redistributions" then allow market mechanisms to create a Pareto efficient outcome. Stiglitz is critical of the prospects of lump sum redistributions; the main basis he cites for this problem is that the government lacks sufficient information to make these redistributions. Stiglitz is also critical of the idea that the decentralized price mechanism could lead to a Pareto efficient allocation of resources. Stiglitz states that "Pareto-efficient allocations cannot generally be obtained without some form of government intervention." Stiglitz concludes of the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics that "efficiency requires not the complete decentralization suggested by the neoclassical paradigm but partial decentralization."
In many regards Stiglitz's critique of the Walrasian view is Hayekian. Throughout The Road to Serfdom Hayek repeats that there is no way that the central planner could have the requisite information to make effective decisions. "What economic actors really do in a market economy is much more complex than what they are postulated to do in the Arrow-Debreu or Walrasian model." Sitglitz and Hayek would agree that economic actors make a myriad of different decisions involving production that could not conceivably be communicated to a central planner. The central planner likewise could not express the correct course of action back to the producers though a directive to maximize profits or an input to output schedule.
While Stiglitz and Hayek would agree that there are fatal problems in applying the Walras model to the informational complex reality, their responses to these problems are in many cases polar opposites. Hayek's answer to the complexities of economic decision making is that the government should as much as is possible disappear from the market. Stiglitz on the other hand is concerned with trying to find the optimal balance between private and public economic activity.

Of Public and Private
One role of government in the market on which Hayek and Stiglitz agree is in the establishment of the rule of law. While they agree that government must establish the rule of law the conclusions to which they come are markedly different. In Hayek's view the rule of law "stripped of all its technicalities," "means that the government in all its actions is bound by rules fixed and announced before hand -rules which make it possible to foresee with fair certainty how the authority will use its coercive powers in given circumstances and to plan one's individual affairs in the basis of this knowledge." Stiglitz writes that "there is one vital role that the government must perform in any economy, and that is establishing the rules of the game - rules that will govern the interactions among private parties and between these private parties and the government." The important difference between Stiglitz and Hayek's conception of the rule of law is the role that the government will play. In Stiglitz's view the government should be an important player in the market. This is totally inconsistent with Hayek's conception of the rule of law. In Hayek's view there cannot be planning (or economic competition) by the government and the rule of law. He feels that "the distinction between the creation of a permanent framework of laws within which the productive activity is guided by individual decisions and the direction of economic activity by a central authority is thus really a particular case of the more general distinction between the rule of law and arbitrary government." Stiglitz presupposes a benevolent government that would create the "rules of the game" and make them apply fairly to both itself and private actors. Hayek takes a more cynical approach to government as an economic actor. He writes that "the planning authority cannot confine itself to providing opportunities for unknown people to make whatever use of them they like. It cannot tie itself down in advance to general and formal rules which prevent arbitrariness." Stiglitz even seems to support some flexibility when he notes of the rule of law that "it is impossible to anticipate every contingency." According to Hayek in a country with a flexible rule of law `contingencies' will arise where government must "decide questions that cannot be answered by formal principles only, and, in making these decisions, it must set up distinctions of merit between the needs of different people."
Hayek is not purporting that there is no role for government in the market, he is strictly concerned with so great a role that it amounts to direction. He notes that "it is important not to confuse opposition against this kind of planning with dogmatic laissez attitude. The liberal argument is in favor of making the best possible use of the forces of competition as a means of co-ordinating human efforts, not an argument for leaving things just as they are." Hayek supports intervention by the government in cases of, what Stiglitz would term, market failures.
The market failures approach argues that there is indeed a role for government, but it is a limited role: Government simply needs to correct the well-defined market failures, which it can do with simple tools having minimal effects on the mode of operation on the economy. For instance, problems of externalities can be addressed through corrective (Pigouvian) taxes. Even when the government is uncertain of the tax rate that will achieve particular pollution control objectives, market mechanisms can be employed: The government can issue marketable pollution permits. To be sure the government has further, limited responsibilities: It might also have to take actions to ensure that markets are actually competitive.
While Stiglitz agrees that governmental involvement in the market is necessary he feels that that the market failures approach is not enough and that a much greater governmental role would be preferable.
Stiglitz divides (or adds in the case of new market failures) market failures into new and old market failures. He defines new market failures as, "market failures, based on imperfect and costly information and incomplete markets" the old market failures are "associated with, for instance, public goods and pollution externalities" and imperfections in competition. Stiglitz agrees that the government is the best mechanism for dealing with the old market failures. Stiglitz even hints that a market socialist system is as effective as capitalism at fixing old market failures "like those concerning air pollution, for which a well defined and effective government policy can often easily be designed." However, he feels that these interventions are not enough. In Stiglitz's view "market failures are indeed pervasive in the economy. They appear in virtually every transaction among private parties in the economy, and while they may be small in each case, cumulatively they are important." Since in the formal sense the market failures approach is intended to internalize externalities to restore Pareto optimality as described in the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics, Stiglitz's informational arguments as described above against the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics apply to the market failures approach and the new market failures as he describes them. While he is concerned with imperfect information, Stiglitz feels that the government is best equipped (better than market mechanisms) to improve Pareto efficiency. Specifically, he believes that "the government's power of compulsion gives it a distinct advantage." According to Stiglitz "when markets are incomplete and information is imperfect, the actions of individuals have externality-like effects on others," and since the government is better equipped to deal with externalities it follows that it would be better equipped to deal with these externality like effects. The (internal) externalities that Stiglitz feels could be improved by government intervention go well beyond those prescribed by Hayek. The following are examples of where Stiglitz feels the government could improve Pareto efficiency through intervention. In incomplete risks markets where anyone can enter production of a commodity the new entrants alter the distribution of returns from the commodity and the "individual's actions in that probability distribution can thus be viewed as an externality." While Stiglitz does not specify how this "externality-like effect" could be internalized, presumably it would involve subsidization, barriers to entry, taxation, or production quotas; though it seems odd that there should be concern for externalities that are internal among producers when market mechanisms would seem to be just as effective if the government did not have perfect information. Incentive (moral hazard) problems like when individuals buy insurance because they are risk adverse, but since they do not have to bear the full costs of the insured against event their incentives to avoid the insured against event are attenuated. According to Stiglitz "this example shows how the government can effect Pareto improvement. By taxing [think cigarettes and triple cheeseburgers] and subsidizing [think stationary bikes and tofu] various commodities, the government can encourage individuals to take greater care." Stiglitz presumes that "while the government and private insurers lack the information necessary to prevent moral hazards--they cannot directly control action--the government has the instruments with which to alleviate the effects of moral hazard and the information required to use those instruments.
Hayek agrees that when there are market failures, of the "old" type as described above, the government has a role in correcting these failures or he would at least agree that the government within limitations should be allowed to correct these failures. Hayek states "to prohibit the use of certain poisonous substances or to require special precautions in their use, to limit working hours or to require certain sanitary arrangements, is fully compatible with preservation of competition. The only question here is whether in the particular instance the advantages gained are better than the social costs which they impose." "But the fact that we have to resort to the substitution of direct regulation by authority where the conditions for the proper workings of competition cannot be created does not prove that we should suppress competition where it can be made to function." Hayek would have no qualms about internalizing the costs of an externality on a business or industry if it would be socially efficient and could not be done through competition. In many cases, however, Hayek would see intrusions by the government as the cause of the apparent externality. As example he cites "the magnificent roads in Germany" as an example where the government has intervened to create technical excellence in a particular field but this excellence is a "misdirection of resources" given the volume of traffic on them compared to the side streets. Hayek may respond to examples of externalities like traffic congestion and pollution by pointing out market distortions caused by governments that stifle or prohibit private road construction and dismiss liability for reductions in property value caused by the pollution.
Hayek would not agree with Stiglitz that there would be a role for government in the "new market failures." The propositions that Stiglitz makes for government expansion would, in Hayek's view, certainly create market distortions. The moral hazards example from above is in perfect contrast with Hayek's view of the role of government. Stiglitz seeks to alleviate the problem of actors who are insulated from risk taking those risks, by creating an additional deterrent in the form of taxes. However, this would create greater market distortions in an insurance scheme since the premiums would be lower based on the higher cost of doing the thing insured against which may entirely offset the higher cost. Stiglitz states that the taxes should be set at a high enough level to prevent these dead weight losses. There is, however, in many cases no tax on goods that would fully eliminate them form the market. Stiglitz curiously states that "while the government and private insurers lack the information necessary to prevent moral hazards--they cannot directly control action--the government has the instruments with which to alleviate the effects of moral hazard and the information required to use those instruments." In Hayek's view the real hazard is that government is in fact quite capable of controlling action and does not have the information required to use instruments to alleviate moral hazards. Hayek is concerned with the lack of information by the government to make judgments on moral hazards. In an insurance moral hazard scheme the insurance companies would presumably have better access to information related to risks and could assign premiums accordingly. Government intervention would require it to presume a comprehensive moral, ethical, and economic code where none exists. "Not only do we not possess such an all inclusive scale values: it would be impossible for any mind to comprehend the infinite variety of different needs of different people which compete for the available resources and to attach a definite weight to each." Of the type of externality like effects that would have to be determined by the moral code envisioned by the government, Hayek gives the example "we could reduce causalities by automobile accidents to zero if we were willing to bear the cost--if in no other way--by abolishing automobiles." Stiglitz it would seem would have the government construct its intervention to prevent moral hazards based solely on economic concerns. Hayek would argue that this type of valuation is not compatible with individualism. While Sitglitz may not ban cars due to their economic uses, he may see taxing them for all uses other than in traveling to and from work and in the transport of commercial goods as an effective intervention into moral hazards.
In regard to financial and management moral hazards Stiglitz has a somewhat Hayekian view though his is interestingly nuanced. Financial moral hazards are where a financial institution is insulated from the hazards of its investments and therefore is more likely to make riskier investments. An example would be if a financial sector became heavily invested in mortgage backed securities whose cash flows are backed by principle and interest payments on subprime mortgages that are unlikely to be paid. If the financial sector suspects that they can receive a government bailout if these investments fail, they are more likely to invest in them since they will reap the benefit of high returns if the investment turns out well but will not have to fully shoulder the burden if the investment fails. Stiglitz terms these financial moral hazards problems "soft budget constraints." Stiglitz emphasizes the need for government's commitment, "particularly its commitment to tough budget constraints." Stiglitz states that "soft budget constraints are like a disease: They can be highly contagious. If the banks face soft budget constraints, they will not impose discipline upon their borrowers." However Stiglitz warns that when faced with hard budget constraints "competent firms may fail the market test as a result of bad luck, and bad firms may pass, as a result of good" so caution must be exercised in establishing hard budget constraints. Of managerial moral hazards Stiglitz notes a variety of problems that arise. Managerial moral hazards can occur when management is shielded from poor decision making. There are problems of accountability and incentives especially in firms where management and ownership are separated. In this situation, managers have incentives to further their career and therefore an incentive to avoid accountability. Managers may be shielded when there are poor decisions in their division but it has a minimal effect on the overall firm. The interesting turn in Stiglitz's view of financial and managerial moral hazards is that government can be just as good (or bad) at addressing them if it is a market player. Stiglitz states that:
Government can create government enterprises that are given hard budget constraints; it can set up a set of procedures that can at least increase the transaction costs associated with softening the budget constraints. It can impose procedures and rules that effectively increase the ability of government enterprises to make commitments. Government-owned corporations can be made to have the same legal status of privately owned corporations, differing only in who owns the shares. While these changes will not obliterate the differences between private and public enterprises, they will reduce their differences, to the point where behavior will be indistinguishable.
This is where Hayek and Stiglitz diverge on financial and management moral hazards. While Hayek would agree with government imposing hard budget constraints and letting competition weed out bad firms he would not believe that the government would do the same for itself if it were a market actor. Hayek notes that "although competition can bear some admixture of regulation, it cannot be combined with planning to any extent we like without ceasing to operate as an effective guide to production." Stiglitz does not address how a government enterprise should be created to eliminate the managerial moral hazards problems associated with private enterprises. Worse yet, he seems to open the door for further moral hazards up to and including abuse by reducing the additional constraints that the populace imposes on government enterprises. The constraints imposed on governments include constraints on wages, outcry at mistakes that waste taxpayer money, aversion to government monopoly, and civil service regulations that restrict the ability to fire workers. Stiglitz writes that "just as greater tolerance of mistakes--or more accurately, the recognition that mistakes are inevitable and costly to avoid--would enhance the efficiency and effectiveness of public organizations, so too would greater tolerance of inequities--or more accurately, the recognition that (perceived) inequalities are inevitable and costly to avoid." Although Stiglitz maintains a cynical view of managers in private enterprise, because of their moral hazards problems, their abuses of public interest and share holders, and their attempts to gain monopoly control to maximize profits, he ignores the implications of adding a governmental monopoly on the power of coercion to the mix. Hayek is not concerned with abuses by private enterprises when they can be made accountable by the government. If, however, the government becomes abusive there is no higher power to make it answerable. Furthermore, this idea of creating a class of workers in government enterprises that are closely tied to the government, leads to a consolidation of governmental power. Every slip by the government outside of fair competition would lead to government enterprises gaining a greater market share and a larger work force identified with the goals of the government. This work force would, in their own interest, be hostile to competition from private firms. "As in the course of the progressive advance toward socialism it becomes more evident to everyone that his income and general position are determined by the coercive apparatus of the state, that he can maintain or improve his position only as a member of an organized group capable of influencing or controlling the state machine in his interest." This snowballing effect will lead to an ever greater portion of the populace identifying themselves with government enterprises in opposition to competition from private competition. As the government gains a majority of market share and a majority of employment, it follows that the perception of what is fair among the populace will shift. If profits from these government enterprises are divided among the entire population the employees of the government enterprises will feel that they are not receiving allocation proportionate to their effort and seek to retain all of the profits, while if the profits are distributed among only the government employees the private sector will seek to join the government apparatus to receive a share of the profits. While Stiglitz is wary that the worst get on top in the leadership in the private sector he seems to presume benevolence from the governmental economic actors. Hayek on the other hand presumes that the same kind of flexible morals that allow the worst to get on top in private corporations are effective in government. Hayek notes that "just as the democratic statesman who sets out to plan economic life will soon be confronted with the alternative of either assuming dictatorial powers or abandoning his plan, so the totalitarian dictator would soon have to choose between disregard of ordinary morals and failure."

Philosophical Speculations against Capitalism
In the Section of Whither Socialism entitled "Philosophical Speculations" Stiglitz attacks the central dogmata of Hayekian economics. In this chapter Stiglitz largely agrees with conventional socialist notions. Stiglitz notes that "one cannot simply dismiss Marxist concerns." Stiglitz rejects the notion, dating back to Adam Smith and beyond, that self-interest is a positive force in society stating that, "capitalism may encourage self-interestedness, but is that desirable?" "By changing the locus of caring and responsibility from the individual to the government--not only for the needy, but for oneself, one's parents, one's children--we change society and we change ourselves" and this redistributive role for government, through the eyes of a chang
7人のお客様がこれが役に立ったと考えています
レポート
Christopher Craig
5つ星のうち4.0 "Shock therepy": all shock, no therepy
2018年8月17日にアメリカ合衆国でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
Interesting to consider recommendations at the time ( 'shock therapy' vs. slow and cautious) with how things have turned
out (so far). Lecturer did not favor shock therapy (recommended by right wing ideologues at the time)
D. W. MacKenzie
5つ星のうち1.0 At the Heels of Giants
2004年6月5日にアメリカ合衆国でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
This book possesses two distinct features. First, it errs frequently. Second, it errs amateurishly. Perhaps the most important error in this book is in how it was researched. It references nothing that Lange and Hayek wrote during the Interwar Debate on Socialism. It references none of the articles that Lerner or Knight published in this debate. It references nothing by Mises, Robbins, Durbin, Dickinson, or Dobb at all. The only article from this debate that Stiglitz read was Taylor's 1929 article- the worst one from the socialist side. Stiglitz also ignores the work of interpreters of this debate. He does not reference Bergson, Heilbroner, Lavoie, Kirzner, T Hoff, Roberts, Murell... In other words, Stiglitz barely scratched the surface of what was actually written in this debate- yet HE claims that THEY did not know what they were talking about. Of course, he did do some research for this book. Stiglitz referenced 126 of his own publications.

The shoddy research of this book shows up in its arguments. Stiglitz refers to the Arrow-Debreu model in discussing the debate between Lange and Hayek. In the ADM scheme of things there is a complete set of markets where unrestricted competition among perfectly informed persons reigns. Naturally, such perfect conditions yield perfect results- on paper. Actual markets do not deliver these results so "the competitive paradigm is not robust" (p107). Of course, it makes no sense to think of the Lange-Hayek debate in terms of Arrow Debreu anyway. This debate over socialism took place mainly in the nineteen thirties. The ADM was published in 1954. Socialism also suffers from incentive problems, so Stiglitz tells us that the Lange-Lerner model of market socialism does not depict reality either. He claims that Lange did not understand the difficulties in allocating capital. In reality, Lange (1938) and Dickinson (1939)wrote explicitly about severe problems in allocating capital.

For those who have actually read and understood the writings of the old socialists, like Lange, Schumpeter, and Dickinson, and their opponents Mises, Hayek, and Robbins this debate looks quite different. All of these economists recognized problems in both systems and wrote about them explicitly. Lange is well known for admitting to the danger of the bureaucratization of economic life under socialism. Hayek stressed the problems with information under both systems, and in fact spelled out the crucial informational imperfections in markets by 1937. Mises, Hayek, Lange, and Schumpeter all thought in dynamic terms that went far beyond the models with which Stiglitz likes to play. Stiglitz tries to reduce Schumpeter's process of creative destruction to a simple (and weak) game theoretic argument. He also ignored Mises completely- this is an unforgivable error.

The main purpose of this book is to play up the importance of its authors prior writings on imperfect information. All past accomplishments on both sides of this debate get recast into a form that makes the author of this book the only one who has made a worthwhile contribution, when in reality it is the contributions of intellectual giants like Hayek, Mises, Lange, Dickinson, and Schumpeter that rise above all else. Modest scholars recognize the shoulders that they stand upon from the past. The author of this book shows little such modesty, and even less in terms of important and original advances. This book should not be taken seriously.
67人のお客様がこれが役に立ったと考えています
レポート