¥9,084 税込
ポイント: 91pt  (1%)  詳細はこちら
無料配送6月11日 火曜日にお届け
詳細を見る
または 最も早いお届け日時指定便 明日 8:00 - 12:00の間にお届け(6 時間 10 分以内にご注文の場合)
詳細を見る
在庫あり。 在庫状況について
¥9,084 () 選択したオプションを含めます。 最初の月の支払いと選択されたオプションが含まれています。 詳細
価格
小計
¥9,084
小計
初期支払いの内訳
レジで表示される配送料、配送日、注文合計 (税込)。
Kindleアプリのロゴ画像

無料のKindleアプリをダウンロードして、スマートフォン、タブレット、またはコンピューターで今すぐKindle本を読むことができます。Kindleデバイスは必要ありません

ウェブ版Kindleなら、お使いのブラウザですぐにお読みいただけます。

携帯電話のカメラを使用する - 以下のコードをスキャンし、Kindleアプリをダウンロードしてください。

KindleアプリをダウンロードするためのQRコード

著者をフォロー

何か問題が発生しました。後で再度リクエストしてください。

Game Theory for Applied Economists ペーパーバック – 1992/7/13

4.5 5つ星のうち4.5 94個の評価

{"desktop_buybox_group_1":[{"displayPrice":"¥9,084","priceAmount":9084.00,"currencySymbol":"¥","integerValue":"9,084","decimalSeparator":null,"fractionalValue":null,"symbolPosition":"left","hasSpace":false,"showFractionalPartIfEmpty":true,"offerListingId":"K4NjQ2vyZ7bkC%2FZ%2Fu3T6jN%2BedLLhvZqD7Iq9Iz6ZGbVJaufoJiehsgatMRuK%2BKxPETKdp5GVgwDznIgnyeHTNKeeVkleA6JVyk7dEd8Gs2%2FjfEtv%2BIpQ%2FxSq5SWY2%2BFj","locale":"ja-JP","buyingOptionType":"NEW","aapiBuyingOptionIndex":0}]}

購入オプションとあわせ買い

商品の説明

レビュー

"[A] lucid and detailed introduction to game theory in an explicitly economic context."-- "Cooperative Economic News Service"

抜粋

Game Theory for Applied Economists

By Robert Gibbons

Princeton University Press

Copyright © 1992 Princeton University Press
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-00395-5

Contents

1 Static Games of Complete Information.................................................11.1 Basic Theory: Normal-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium...............................21.1.A Normal-Form Representation of Games..............................................21.1.B Iterated Elimination of Strictly Dominated Strategies............................41.1.C Motivation and Definition of Nash Equilibrium....................................81.2 Applications.......................................................................141.2.A Cournot Model of Duopoly.........................................................141.2.B Bertrand Model of Duopoly........................................................211.2.C Final-Offer Arbitration..........................................................221.2.D The Problem of the Commons.......................................................271.3 Advanced Theory: Mixed Strategies and Existence of Equilibrium.....................291.3.A Mixed Strategies.................................................................291.3.B Existence of Nash Equilibrium....................................................331.4 Further Reading....................................................................481.5 Problems...........................................................................481.6 References.........................................................................512 Dynamic Games of Complete Information................................................552.1 Dynamic Games of Complete and Perfect Information..................................572.1.A Theory: Backwards Induction......................................................572.1.B Stackelberg Model of Duopoly.....................................................612.1.C Wages and Employment in a Unionized Firm.........................................642.1.D Sequential Bargaining............................................................682.2 Two-Stage Games of Complete but Imperfect Information..............................712.2.A Theory: Subgame Perfection.......................................................712.2.B Bank Runs........................................................................732.2.C Tariffs and Imperfect International Competition..................................752.2.D Tournaments......................................................................792.3 Repeated Games.....................................................................822.3.A Theory: Two-Stage Repeated Game..................................................s 822.3.B Theory: Infinitely Repeated Games................................................882.3.C Collusion between Cournot Duopolists.............................................1022.3.D Efficiency Wages.................................................................1072.3.E Time-Consistent Monetary Policy..................................................1122.4 Dynamic Games of Complete but Imperfect Information................................1152.4.A Extensive-Form Representation of Games...........................................1152.4.B Subgame-Perfect Nash Equilibrium.................................................1222.5 Further Reading....................................................................1292.6 Problems...........................................................................1302.7 References.........................................................................1383 Static Games of Incomplete Information...............................................1433.1 Theory: Static Bayesian Games and Bayesian Nash Equilibrium........................1443.1.A An Example: Cournot Competition under Asymmetric Information.....................1443.1.B Normal-Form Representation of Static Bayesian Games..............................1463.1.C Definition of Bayesian Nash Equilibrium..........................................1493.2 Applications.......................................................................1523.2.A Mixed Strategies Revisited.......................................................1523.2.B An Auction.......................................................................1553.2.C A Double Auction.................................................................1583.3 The Revelation Principle...........................................................1643.4 Further Reading....................................................................1683.5 Problems...........................................................................1693.6 References.........................................................................1724 Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information..............................................1734.1 Introduction to Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium.......................................1754.2 Signaling Games....................................................................1834.2.A Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium in Signaling Games..................................1834.2.B Job-Market Signaling.............................................................1904.2.C Corporate Investment and Capital Structure.......................................2054.2.D Monetary Policy..................................................................2084.3 Other Applications of Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium.................................2104.3.A Cheap-Talk Games.................................................................2104.3.B Sequential Bargaining under Asymmetric Information...............................2184.3.C Reputation in the Finitely Repeated Prisoners' Dilemma...........................2244.4 Refinements of Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium........................................2334.5 Further Reading....................................................................2444.6 Problems...........................................................................2454.7 References.........................................................................253Index..................................................................................257

Chapter One

Static Games of Complete Information

In this chapter we consider games of the following simple form: first the players simultaneously choose actions; then the players receive payoffs that depend on the combination of actions just chosen. Within the class of such static (or simultaneous-move) games, we restrict attention to games of complete information. That is, each player's payoff function (the function that determines the player's payoff from the combination of actions chosen by the players) is common knowledge among all the players. We consider dynamic (or sequential-move) games in Chapters 2 and 4, and games of incomplete information (games in which some player is uncertain about another player's payoff function-as in an auction where each bidder's willingness to pay for the good being sold is unknown to the other bidders) in Chapters 3 and 4.

In Section 1.1 we take a first pass at the two basic issues in game theory: how to describe a game and how to solve the resulting game-theoretic problem. We develop the tools we will use in analyzing static games of complete information, and also the foundations of the theory we will use to analyze richer games in later chapters. We define the normal-form representation of a game and the notion of a strictly dominated strategy. We show that some games can be solved by applying the idea that rational players do not play strictly dominated strategies, but also that in other games this approach produces a very imprecise prediction about the play of the game (sometimes as imprecise as "anything could happen"). We then motivate and define Nash equilibrium-a solution concept that produces much tighter predictions in a very broad class of games.

In Section 1.2 we analyze four applications, using the tools developed in the previous section: Cournot's (1838) model of imperfect competition, Bertrand's (1883) model of imperfect competition, Farber's (1980) model of final-offer arbitration, and the problem of the commons (discussed by Hume [1739] and others). In each application we first translate an informal statement of the problem into a normal-form representation of the game and then solve for the game's Nash equilibrium. (Each of these applications has a unique Nash equilibrium, but we discuss examples in which this is not true.)

In Section 1.3 we return to theory. We first define the notion of a mixed strategy, which we will interpret in terms of one player's uncertainty about what another player will do. We then state and discuss Nash's (1950) Theorem, which guarantees that a Nash equilibrium (possibly involving mixed strategies) exists in a broad class of games. Since we present first basic theory in Section 1.1, then applications in Section 1.2, and finally more theory in Section 1.3, it should be apparent that mastering the additional theory in Section 1.3 is not a prerequisite for understanding the applications in Section 1.2. On the other hand, the ideas of a mixed strategy and the existence of equilibrium do appear (occasionally) in later chapters.

This and each subsequent chapter concludes with problems, suggestions for further reading, and references.

1.1 Basic Theory: Normal-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium

1.1.A Normal-Form Representation of Games

In the normal-form representation of a game, each player simultaneously chooses a strategy, and the combination of strategies chosen by the players determines a payoff for each player. We illustrate the normal-form representation with a classic example - The Prisoners' Dilemma. Two suspects are arrested and charged with a crime. The police lack sufficient evidence to convict the suspects, unless at least one confesses. The police hold the suspects in separate cells and explain the consequences that will follow from the actions they could take. If neither confesses then both will be convicted of a minor offense and sentenced to one month in jail. If both confess then both will be sentenced to jail for six months. Finally, if one confesses but the other does not, then the confessor will be released immediately but the other will be sentenced to nine months in jail-six for the crime and a further three for obstructing justice.

The prisoners' problem can be represented in the accompanying bi-matrix. (Like a matrix, a bi-matrix can have an arbitrary number or rows and columns; "bi" refers to the fact that, in a two-player game, there are two numbers in each cell-the payoffs to the two players.)

In this game, each player has two strategies available: confess (or fink) and not confess (or be mum). The payoffs to the two players when a particular pair of strategies is chosen are given in the appropriate cell of the bi-matrix. By convention, the payoff to the so-called row player (here, Prisoner 1) is the first payoff given, followed by the payoff to the column player (here, Prisoner 2). Thus, if Prisoner 1 chooses Mum and Prisoner 2 chooses Fink, for example, then Prisoner 1 receives the payoff -9 (representing nine months in jail) and Prisoner 2 receives the payoff 0 (representing immediate release).

We now turn to the general case. The normal-form representation of a game specifies: (1) the players in the game, (2) the strategies available to each player, and (3) the payoff received by each player for each combination of strategies that could be chosen by the players. We will often discuss an n-player game in which the players are numbered from 1 to n and an arbitrary player is called player i. Let [S.sub.i] denote the set of strategies available to player i (called i's strategy space), and let s, denote an arbitrary member of this set. (We will occasionally write [s.sub.i] [member of] [S.sub.i], to indicate that the strategy [s.sub.i], is a member of the set of strategies [S.sub.i].) Let ([s.sub.i], ..., [s.sub.n]) denote a combination of strategies, one for each player, and let [u.sub.i] denote player i's payoff function: [u.sub.i]([S.sub.1], ..., [s.sub.n]) is the payoff to player i if the players choose the strategies ([s.sub.i], ..., [s.sub.n]). Collecting all of this information together, we have:

Definition The normal-form representation of an n-player game specifies the players' strategy spaces [S.sub.1], ..., [S.sub.n] and their payoff functions [u.sub.1], ..., [u.sub.n]. We denote this game by G = {[S.sub.i], ..., [S.sub.n];[u.sub.i], ..., [u.sub.n]}.

Although we stated that in a normal-form game the players choose their strategies simultaneously, this does not imply that the parties necessarily act simultaneously: it suffices that each choose his or her action without knowledge of the others' choices, as would be the case here if the prisoners reached decisions at arbitrary times while in their separate cells. Furthermore, although in this chapter we use normal-form games to represent only static games in which the players all move without knowing the other players' choices, we will see in Chapter 2 that normal-form representations can be given for sequential-move games, but also that an alternative-the extensive-form representation of the game-is often a more convenient framework for analyzing dynamic issues.

1.1.B Iterated Elimination of Strictly Dominated Strategies

Having described one way to represent a game, we now take a first pass at describing how to solve a game-theoretic problem. We start with the Prisoners' Dilemma because it is easy to solve, using only the idea that a rational player will not play a strictly dominated strategy.

In the Prisoners' Dilemma, if one suspect is going to play Fink, then the other would prefer to play Fink and so be in jail for six months rather than play Mum and so be in jail for nine months. Similarly, if one suspect is going to play Mum, then the other would prefer to play Fink and so be released immediately rather than play Mum and so be in jail for one month. Thus, for prisoner i, playing Mum is dominated by playing Fink-for each strategy that prisoner j could choose, the payoff to prisoner i from playing Mum is less than the payoff to i from playing Fink. (The same would be true in any bi-matrix in which the payoffs 0, -1, -6, and -9 above were replaced with payoffs T, R, P, and S, respectively, provided that T > R > P > S so as to capture the ideas of temptation, reward, punishment, and sucker payoffs.) More generally:

Definition In the normal-form game G = {[S.sub.1], ..., [S.sub.n]; [u.sub.1], ..., [u.sub.n]}, let [s'.sub.i] and [s".sub.i] be feasible strategies for player i (i.e., [s'.sub.i] and [s".sub.i] are members of [S.sub.i]). Strategy [s'.sub.i] is strictly dominated by strategy [s".sub.i] if for each feasible combination of the other players' strategies, i's payoff from playing [s'.sub.i] is strictly less than i's payoff from playing [s".sub.i]:

[u.sub.i]([s.sub.1], ..., [s.sub.i] - 1, [s'.sub.i], [s.sub.i+1], ..., [s.sub.n]) <[u.sub.i] ([s.sub.1], ..., [s.sub.i-1], [s".sub.i], [s.sub.i+1], ..., [s.sub.n]) (DS)

for each ([s.sub.1], ..., [s.sub.i-1], [s.sub.i+1], ..., [s.sub.n]) that can be constructed from the other players' strategy spaces [S.sub.1], ..., [S.sub.i-1], [S.sub.i+1], ..., [S.sub.n].

Rational players do not play strictly dominated strategies, because there is no belief that a player could hold (about the strategies the other players will choose) such that it would be optimal to play such a strategy. Thus, in the Prisoners' Dilemma, a rational player will choose Fink, so (Fink, Fink) will be the outcome reached by two rational players, even though (Fink, Fink) results in worse payoffs for both players than would (Mum, Mum). Because the Prisoners' Dilemma has many applications (including the arms race and the free-rider problem in the provision of public goods), we will return to variants of the game in Chapters 2 and 4. For now, we focus instead on whether the idea that rational players do not play strictly dominated strategies can lead to the solution of other games.

Consider the abstract game in Figure 1.1.1. Player 1 has two strategies and player 2 has three: [S.sub.1] = {Up, Down} and [S.sub.2] = {Left, Middle, Right}. For player 1, neither Up nor Down is strictly dominated: Up is better than Down if 2 plays Left (because 1 > 0), but Down is better than Up if 2 plays Right (because 2 > 0). For player 2, however, Right is strictly dominated by Middle (because 2 > 1 and 1 > 0), so a rational player 2 will not play Right. Thus, if player 1 knows that player 2 is rational then player 1 can eliminate Right from player 2's strategy space. That is, if player 1 knows that player 2 is rational then player 1 can play the game in Figure 1.1.1 as if it were the game in Figure 1.1.2.

In Figure 1.1.2, Down is now strictly dominated by Up for player 1, so if player 1 is rational (and player 1 knows that player 2 is rational, so that the game in Figure 1.1.2 applies) then player 1 will not play Down. Thus, if player 2 knows that player 1 is rational, and player 2 knows that player 1 knows that player 2 is rational (so that player 2 knows that Figure 1.1.2 applies), then player 2 can eliminate Down from player 1's strategy space, leaving the game in Figure 1.1.3. But now Left is strictly dominated by Middle for player 2, leaving (Up, Middle) as the outcome of the game.

This process is called iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies. Although it is based on the appealing idea that rational players do not play strictly dominated strategies, the process has two drawbacks. First, each step requires a further assumption about what the players know about each other's rationality. If we want to be able to apply the process for an arbitrary number of steps, we need to assume that it is common knowledge that the players are rational. That is, we need to assume not only that all the players are rational, but also that all the players know that all the players are rational, and that all the players know that all the players know that all the players are rational, and so on, ad infinitum. (See Aumann [1976] for the formal definition of common knowledge.)

The second drawback of iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies is that the process often produces a very imprecise prediction about the play of the game. Consider the game in Figure 1.1.4, for example. In this game there are no strictly dominated strategies to be eliminated. (Since we have not motivated this game in the slightest, it may appear arbitrary, or even pathological. See the case of three or more firms in the Cournot model in Section 1.2.A for an economic application in the same spirit.) Since all the strategies in the game survive iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies, the process produces no prediction whatsoever about the play of the game.

We turn next to Nash equilibrium-a solution concept that produces much tighter predictions in a very broad class of games. We show that Nash equilibrium is a stronger solution concept than iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies, in the sense that the players' strategies in a Nash equilibrium always survive iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies, but the converse is not true. In subsequent chapters we will argue that in richer games even Nash equilibrium produces too imprecise a prediction about the play of the game, so we will define still-stronger notions of equilibrium that are better suited for these richer games.

1.1.C Motivation and Definition of Nash Equilibrium

One way to motivate the definition of Nash equilibrium is to argue that if game theory is to provide a unique solution to a game-theoretic problem then the solution must be a Nash equilibrium, in the following sense. Suppose that game theory makes a unique prediction about the strategy each player will choose. In order for this prediction to be correct, it is necessary that each player be willing to choose the strategy predicted by the theory. Thus, each player's predicted strategy must be that player's best response to the predicted strategies of the other players. Such a prediction could be called strategically stable or self-enforcing, because no single player wants to deviate from his or her predicted strategy. We will call such a prediction a Nash equilibrium:

Definition In the n-player normal-form game G = {[S.sub.1], ..., [S.sub.n]; [u.sub.1], ..., [u.sub.n]], the strategies ([s.sup.*.sub.1], ..., [s.sup.*.sub.n]) are a Nash equilibrium if, for each player i, [s.sup.*.sub.i] is (at least tied for) player i's best response to the strategies specified for the n - 1 other players, ([s.sup.*.sub.1], ..., [s.sup.*.sub.i-1], [s.sup.*.sub.i+1], ..., [s.sup.*.sub.n]}:

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (NE)

for every feasible strategy [s.sub.i] in [S.sub.i]; that is, [s.sup.*.sub.i] solves

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

To relate this definition to its motivation, suppose game theory offers the strategies ([s'.sub.1], ..., [s'.sub.n]) as the solution to the normal-form game G = {[S.sub.1], ..., [S.sub.n]; [u.sub.1], ..., [u.sub.n]}. Saying that ([s'.sub.1], ..., [s'.sub.n]) is not a Nash equilibrium of G is equivalent to saying that there exists some player i such that [s'.sub.i] is not a best response to ([s'.sub.1], ..., [s'.sub.i-1], [s'.sub.i+1], ..., [s'.sub.n]). That is, there exists some [s".sub.i] in [S.sub.i], such that

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

Thus, if the theory offers the strategies ([s'.sub.1], ..., [s'.sub.n]) as the solution but these strategies are not a Nash equilibrium, then at least one player will have an incentive to deviate from the theory's prediction, so the theory will be falsified by the actual play of the game. A closely related motivation for Nash equilibrium involves the idea of convention: if a convention is to develop about how to play a given game then the strategies prescribed by the convention must be a Nash equilibrium, else at least one player will not abide by the convention.

(Continues...)


Excerpted from Game Theory for Applied Economistsby Robert Gibbons Copyright © 1992 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

登録情報

  • 出版社 ‏ : ‎ Princeton University Press; Reprint版 (1992/7/13)
  • 発売日 ‏ : ‎ 1992/7/13
  • 言語 ‏ : ‎ 英語
  • ペーパーバック ‏ : ‎ 284ページ
  • ISBN-10 ‏ : ‎ 0691003955
  • ISBN-13 ‏ : ‎ 978-0691003955
  • 寸法 ‏ : ‎ 15.6 x 1.52 x 23.39 cm
  • カスタマーレビュー:
    4.5 5つ星のうち4.5 94個の評価

著者について

著者をフォローして、新作のアップデートや改善されたおすすめを入手してください。
Robert Gibbons
Brief content visible, double tap to read full content.
Full content visible, double tap to read brief content.

著者の本をもっと発見したり、よく似た著者を見つけたり、著者のブログを読んだりしましょう

カスタマーレビュー

星5つ中4.5つ
5つのうち4.5つ
全体的な星の数と星別のパーセンテージの内訳を計算するにあたり、単純平均は使用されていません。当システムでは、レビューがどの程度新しいか、レビュー担当者がAmazonで購入したかどうかなど、特定の要素をより重視しています。 詳細はこちら
94グローバルレーティング

この商品をレビュー

他のお客様にも意見を伝えましょう

上位レビュー、対象国: 日本

2010年11月16日に日本でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
6人のお客様がこれが役に立ったと考えています
レポート
2003年11月22日に日本でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
7人のお客様がこれが役に立ったと考えています
レポート

他の国からのトップレビュー

すべてのレビューを日本語に翻訳
Richard Phu
5つ星のうち5.0 dope af
2021年8月19日にカナダでレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
Amazon Customer
5つ星のうち4.0 as described
2017年3月17日にフランスでレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
Karina
5つ星のうち5.0 Five Stars
2016年9月10日に英国でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
NWcaliMOM
5つ星のうち5.0 Great Level of Detail
2013年1月23日にアメリカ合衆国でレビュー済み
Amazonで購入
3人のお客様がこれが役に立ったと考えています
レポート
Mike H
5つ星のうち5.0 Fantastic condensed guide to Game Theory
2017年1月6日にカナダでレビュー済み
Amazonで購入